5

 

 

 

 

              The Evolution of Societies

                   and World-Systems

 

 

                 Stephen K. Sanderson

 

 

 

 

 

 

INTRODUCTION

 

 

Evolutionary theories of human social life

continue to be much debated in modern social

science.  Although there are still many advo-

cates of these theories, especially among

anthropologists, we are currently in a period

in which such theories are unpopular among

sociologists.  This unpopularity stems from a

wide range of criticisms, but clearly one of

the most important is the belief that evolu-

tionary theories are unacceptably endogenist -

- that they view social evolution as a process

occurring fundamentally within the bounds of

reasonably well-defined societies (cf. Nisbet,

1969; Giddens, 1981, 1984).

   As a result of this criticism, many histor-

ically inclined sociologists have turned away

from the analysis of individual societies and

in the direction of larger constellations of

societies.  Thus the creation by Immanuel

Wallerstein in the early 1970s of world-system

theory, a type of theory in which individual

societies are viewed, not as autonomous, but

as inserted into the operation of a larger

network.  It is this network -- the world--

system -- that is then said to be the only

proper unit of analysis, with the fate of

individual societies being determined princi-

pally by their involvement in the world-system

as a whole.

   Wallerstein's concern has been with the

modern capitalist world- economy that he

envisages as originating in Europe in the

sixteenth century and he has shown very little

interest in the precapitalist era.  However,

the great appeal of his theory has led other

social scientists to attempt to apply the

concept of a world-system to the entire pre-

capitalist era.  It is thus claimed that

Wallerstein's basic argument can be general-

ized backward in time: There were precapi-

talist world-systems, and the understanding of

world history must focus on the operation of

these systems rather than on individual soci-

eties.

   Many world-system enthusiasts see their

work as antievolutionary, or at least nonevol-

utionary, in nature.  Since they view evolu-

tionary theories as endogenist theories, they

see themselves as setting up an explicitly

exogenist (and thus nonevolutionary) alterna-

tive.  However, I hope to show that such a

notion is based on a false distinction and a

misunderstanding of the nature of social

evolutionism.  While evolutionary  theories

have historically given pride of place to

endogenous factors, such theories need not be

endogenist.  They can give equal attention to

endogenous and exogenous factors, or even be

highly exogenist.  Indeed, I shall argue that

Wallerstein's world-system theory is a quinte-

ssentially evolutionary theory. If I am right

-- if one can be a Wallersteinian and an

evolutionist at the same time -- then it is

quite possible to take an evolutionary ap-

proach to understanding precapitalist world-

systems.  To do so involves demonstrating two

fundamental things.  It must first be shown

that there really were precapitalist world-

systems in some meaningful sense of that term.

And, if this can be done, one must then try to

identify the kind of "evolutionary logic"

these systems contained.  For, after all, this

is exactly what Wallerstein has done for his

capitalist world-system -- it is what makes

him a type of evolutionist -- and thus if we

are to apply his ideas successfully to the

precapitalist era it is incumbent upon us to

do the same.

   Unfortunately, I shall be forced to con-

clude that this effort to construct an evolu-

tionary analysis of precapitalist world-sys-

tems produces, at best, very mixed results.

There are some types of precapitalist world-

systems, but they differ in some very impor-

tant respects from the modern capitalist

world-economy.  Moreover, much of the social

evolution that has occurred in the precapital-

ist era, as well as in the transition to the

capitalist era itself, suggests that the

proper unit of analysis is not some sort of

world-system, but rather something much more

akin to the individual society of more tradi-

tional evolutionary analyses.  Are world-

systems or individual societies the proper

unit of evolutionary analysis?  Which are more

important determinants of social evolution,

exogenous or endogenous factors?  As we shall

see, the answers to these questions depend

upon the historical period and the type of

social system with which we are dealing.

 

 

 

 

WHAT IS AN EVOLUTIONARY THEORY?

 

 

In order to establish the point that there is

no inherent antagonism between an evolutionary

and a world-system perspective, and that

Wallerstein's world-system theory is a type of

evolutionism, we first need a proper under-

standing of what an evolutionary theory actu-

ally is.  There is, in fact, much misunder-

standing on this count, a good deal of which I

have reviewed elsewhere (cf. Sanderson, 1990).

Because of space limitations, I shall confine

myself here to a simple exposition of what I

take to be the best definition of an evolu-

tionary theory, that of Erik Olin Wright

(1983).  Wright suggests that for a theory to

be considered evolutionary it must have three

features: (1) It must propose a typology of

social forms with potential directionality.

(2) It must order these social forms in the

way it does on the assumption that the proba-

bility of remaining at the same stage in the

typology is greater than the probability of

regressing.  (3) It must assert a probability

of  transition from one stage of the typology

to another.  It therefore claims the existence

of a tendency toward directionality, no matter

how weak, in social change.  It is also clear

that Wright demands the presence of a mecha-

nism that would explain such a directional

tendency.  However, this need not be a single

universal mechanism that would explain every

specific evolutionary transition.  He recog-

nizes that "the actual mechanisms which might

explain movement between adjacent forms on the

typology need not be the same at every stage

of the typology" (Wright, 1983:26-27).

   As Wright is at pains to point out, his way

of identifying an evolutionary theory makes no

claim that the typology of social forms repre-

sents a teleological unfolding of latent

potentialities, something many critics of

evolutionism falsely assume to be basic to an

evolutionary theory.  Nor does it claim that

such a typology represents a rigid sequence of

stages through which all societies must move.

Wright does not even assume that all (or even

most) societies necessarily evolve. Regression

is entirely permitted, and it is fully ac-

knowledged that in most societies "long-term

steady states may be more likely than any

systematic tendency for movement" (Wright,

1983:26).

 

 

 

 

WORLD-SYSTEM THEORY AS SOCIAL EVOLUTIONISM

 

 

I believe that Wright has come closer than

anyone else to pinpointing the genuinely

irreducible features of an evolutionary theo-

ry.  Using his characterization of an evolu-

tionary theory, it can be shown that Waller-

stein's world-system theory is evolutionary in

a thoroughgoing way.  Of course, this approach

to historical change is scarcely thought of as

evolutionary, and in fact is often identified

as strongly antievolutionary.  The painstaking

detail with which Wallerstein has, in the

three volumes of The Modern World-System

(1974a, 1980, 1989), analyzed historical

events seems strikingly at odds with the works

of social evolutionists.  Moreover, Waller-

stein has frequently cited with approval the

basic arguments of Robert Nisbet's Social

Change and History (1969), no doubt the lead-

ing antievolutionary work written by a sociol-

ogist in the past quarter-century.  Surely

Wallerstein cannot be an evolutionist.

   In fact, though, he is, and very decidedly

so.  What has thrown people off the track

about Wallerstein involves his condemnation of

the sort of evolutionism that reigned supreme

in American social science in the 1950s and

1960s.  But Wallerstein is opposed only to

this particular type of evolutionism and to

other versions that share key features in

common with it.  He is only opposed to what he

has called the developmentalist perspective,

by which he means functionalist evolutionism

(and its modernization variant) and certain

rigidly unilinearist versions of Marxist

evolutionism.  As he has said, "What thus

distinguishes the developmentalist and the

world-system perspective is not liberalism

versus Marxism nor evolutionism  versus some-

thing else (since both are essentially evolu-

tionary)" (1979:54; emphasis added).

   Careful analysis of Wallerstein's works,

especially some of his theoretical essays,

clearly reveals that he means what he says

when he describes his world-system perspective

as a type of evolutionism.  Following Wright,

an evolutionary theory is minimally one that

defines some general directional trend in

history.  The history Wallerstein is interest-

ed in is that of capitalism since the six-

teenth century, and for him capitalism most

assuredly has an overall directionality to it.

It is of course, a directionality of the

world-system as a single unit rather than

individual societies or nation-states.  These

latter evolve only as parts of the whole.

   Along what lines is the capitalist world-

economy evolving?  Wallerstein (1984a) tells

us that there are three main directional

trends involved: increasing mechanization of

production, increasing commodification of the

factors of production (which includes as a

very important element the increasing prole-

tarianization of the labor force), and in-

creasing contractualization of economic rela-

tionships.  These three trends are part and

parcel of a "deepening" of capitalist develop-

ment, a deepening that derives from the accum-

ulationist motivations of capitalist entrepre-

neurs.  It is this drive for the accumulation

of capital that constitutes the "evolutionary

logic" of modern capitalism -- the "motor"

that drives it from one stage to another.

   Furthermore, Wallerstein has not shied away

from the identification of specific stages in

the evolution of the capitalist world-system

(cf. Wallerstein, 1974b).  The first stage

(approximately 1450-1640) involves the emer-

gence of capitalism from the crisis of feudal-

ism and its initial expansion to cover signif-

icant portions of the globe.  The second stage

(roughly 1640-1750) is a stage of the "consol-

idation" of the world-system.  The third stage

(about 1750-1917) marks the eruption of indus-

trial capitalism.  It is a period of renewed

expansion of the world-system, which by the

end of this period covers virtually the entire

globe.  The fourth stage began with the Rus-

sian Revolution and is a stage of the "consol-

idation" of the industrial capitalist world-

economy.

   I also think it is very obvious that Wal-

lerstein has retained a great deal of what

might be called Marx's "evolutionary eschato-

logy."  Like Marx, Wallerstein is convinced

that capitalism is essentially evil, that it

is rife with contradictions that will tear it

apart in the end, and that when it collapses

it will lead to something more humane.  It is

just that all of this occurs on a world rather

than a national scale.  The gap between core

and periphery continues to widen, and this

spawns "antisystemic movements" that increas-

ingly threaten the continued viability of the

system.  Within the next 100-150 years capi-

talism will disintegrate and will be replaced

by, most likely, a socialist world-government.

What will this world-government be like?

Wallerstein describes it in terms that are

highly evocative of Marx (1984b:157):

 

 

   The idea is that on the basis of an ad-

   vanced technology, capable of providing

   a rate of global production adequate to

   meet the total needs of all the world's

   population, the rate and forms of pro-

   duction will be the result of collective

   decisions made in virtue of these needs.

   Furthermore, it is believed that the

   amount of new labor-time to maintain

   such a level of productivity will be

   sufficiently low as to permit each indi-

   vidual the time and resources to engage

   in activities aimed at fulfilling his

   potential.

 

 

   The global production required will be

   attained, not merely because of the

   technological base, but because the

   egalitarian collectivity will be inter-

   ested in realizing the full "potential

   surplus."  This being the case, the

   social motivations for collective ag-

   gressive behavior will have disappeared,

   even if, in the beginning phases, not

   all the psychological motivations will

   have done so.  Since collective deci-

   sions will be pursued in the common

   interest, then worldwide ecological

   balance will follow as an inherent ob-

   jective.

 

 

   In short, the socialist mode of produc-

   tion seeks to fulfill the objective of

   the rational and free society which was

   the ideological mask of the capitalist

   world-economy.  In such a situation,

   repressive state machinery will have no

   function and will over time transform

   itself into routine administration.

 

 

Marx thus turns out in the end to be basically

right in his prediction of the evolutionary

demise of capitalism.  It is just that he had

his units of analysis mixed up, and so he

failed to gauge accurately the timing of the

transition from capitalism to socialism.

   It must be recognized that Wallerstein's

evolutionism is certainly of a complex sort.

Mixed in with his evolutionism is a strong

emphasis on economic cycles (Kondratieff

waves).  But this does not vitiate my claim

that Wallerstein's basic framework is evolu-

tionary -- it only qualifies it.  There is no

incompatibility between an emphasis on cycli-

cal rhythms and an evolutionary perspective,

because the cycles occur within (and are basic

to) the overall directional trends of the

capitalist world-economy.

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

WERE THERE PRECAPITALIST WORLD-SYSTEMS?

 

 

The enormous success of Wallerstein's world-

system model quickly led some social scien-

tists to ask whether it might have more gener-

al applicability.  One of the first to do so

was Jane Schneider (chapter 2, this volume;

orig. 1977).  Schneider  claimed that one of

the main difficulties with Wallerstein's work

was that it "suffers from too narrow an appli-

cation of its own theory" (1977:20).  That is,

it sees the capitalist world-economy as having

no parallels during the precapitalist era.

Schneider went on to argue that one of the

reasons for Wallerstein's stance on this

matter concerns his distinction between the

exchange of fundamental goods and the exchange

of preciosities, and his insistence that a

world-economy is based on the former rather

than the latter.  Indeed, for Wallerstein the

exchange of preciosities is something that is

nonsystemic, or that occurs between a world-

economy and its external arena. This leads him

to exclude precapitalist Europe from involve-

ment in a world-economy, since its exchanges

with other regions were exchanges of luxuries

rather than fundamental goods.

   Schneider objected to Wallerstein's diminu-

tion of the importance of trade in preciosi-

ties.  She claimed that such a trade is of

much greater significance than Wallerstein was

willing to grant, and that therefore it is

"possible to hypothesize a precapitalist

world-system, in which core areas accumulated

precious metals while exporting manufactures,

whereas peripheral areas gave up these metals

(and often slaves) against an inflow of fin-

ished goods" (1977:25).  She saw precapitalist

Europe as deeply involved in a larger world-

system in which it was peripheral to the

better established civilizations of the Levant

and Asia.  She also saw the existence of such

a Eurasian world-system as having significance

for the historical transition from feudalism

to capitalism in Europe, viewing the transi-

tion as a world-system event rather than an

endogenous evolution of feudal Europe.  Within

the Eurasian world-system, she claimed, Europe

shifted its position from periphery to core

over many centuries, eventually becoming

dominant over those areas to which it previ-

ously had been subordinated.

   Other scholars were soon to follow Schnei-

der's lead.  In a long essay, Jonathan Fried-

man and Michael Rowlands (1978) made the

notion of "external relations" central to

understanding the original rise of civiliza-

tion.  According to them (1978:271):

 

 

   The development of the early central

   civilizations clearly depended on the

   productive activity of very large areas,

   and in order to fully understand the

   evolutionary process it is necessary to

   take account of these larger systems of

   reproduction.  The transformation of

   societies does not occur in a vacuum and

   the relation between units in a larger

   system may determine the conditions of

   evolution of any one of them.

 

 

This idea has been substantially elaborated by

Friedman and Kajsa Ekholm (Ekholm and Fried-

man, 1982; Ekholm, 1981).  Ekholm and Friedman

see world-systems as very general historical

phenomena, and as the basic unit to which

evolutionary analyses should apply.  Ekholm

denies the relevance of focusing on individual

societies, claiming that "evolution occurs

only at  the level of the system as a whole"

(1981:245).  Like Schneider, Ekholm applies

this idea to understanding the European tran-

sition from feudalism to capitalism:  "Thus

the development of capitalism in Europe is not

the result of an evolution from feudalism as a

system, but the result of a shift in accumula-

tion from east to west in a single system"

(Ekholm, 1981:245).

   At the moment the scholar most vigorously

pursuing a world-system approach to the devel-

opment of Western capitalism is Janet Abu-

Lughod (1988, 1989).  Abu-Lughod claims that

by the middle of the thirteenth century there

existed a world-system centered around long-

distance trade that had a strongly capitalis-

tic character.  This system consisted of eight

subsystems, and the "kingpin of the entire

system lay at the land bridge between the

eastern Mediterranean and the outlets to the

Indian Ocean on the south and between the

Mediterranean and Central Asia" (1988:10).  At

this time Asia was at least on a par with, and

perhaps in a more favorable position than,

Europe.  What happened in the centuries ahead

to change all that? Abu-Lughod insists that to

answer this question we should not look, as

most Western scholars have, to the internal

features of Europe and Asia to see why the

former surpassed the latter. Rather, we should

focus on the interactions among the subsystems

of the entire world-system.  She argues that

the rise to economic dominance of northwest

Europe resulted from geopolitical shifts in

the relations among crucial subsystems (Abu-

Lughod, 1988:11):  "When the large system

tipped, it was because the Mediterranean

northwestern European links deepened and

diversified while the link between the eastern

Mediterranean and the Orient began to fray in

places and was rudely torn in others."

   The notion of precapitalist world-systems

has continued to find strong proponents.  In

1987 an important volume of conference procee-

dings was published on this topic (Rowlands,

Larsen, and Kristiansen, 1987).  The authors

of the individual essays tried to demonstrate

the existence of world-systemic networks in

ancient times in such places as the ancient

Near East, Scandinavia, and ancient Rome.

Perhaps the strongest proponent of the idea of

precapitalist world-systems is Christopher

Chase-Dunn (1986), who has gone considerably

beyond previous work in attempting to develop

an elaborate typology of world-systems (see

also Chase-Dunn and Hall, chapter 1, this

volume).  Chase-Dunn suggests six basic types

of world-systems:  (1) stateless world-sys-

tems, in which bands, tribes, and chiefdoms

are engaged in various types of economic

exchange;  (2) primary world-economies, which

involve regional systems of core/periphery

specialization among the pristine states, but

without any imperial political structure;  (3)

primary world-empires, or the earliest forms

of core/periphery specialization to have

acquired an imperial political structure;  (4)

complex secondary world-systems, in which

primary world-empires were combined into

larger world-empires;  (5) commercializing

world-systems, or precapitalist world-systems

with an unusually high level of commercializa-

tion or "premodern  capitalism";  (6)  the

capitalist world-economy, which rose to domi-

nance via a shift of influence within the

larger "super world-system" that preceded it.

   This typology has much to recommend it,

especially in giving us food for thought in

dealing with questions of social evolution,

but some cautions seem in order.  First, the

whole notion of stateless world-systems ap-

pears questionable.  This is not to deny that

bands, tribes, and chiefdoms have engaged in

significant levels of economic exchange with

each other, nor is it to deny that these

exchanges may have influenced the evolutionary

trajectories of the individual societies.  The

problem is that, in order for us to use the

concept of world-system at all meaningfully,

there must be more than just a larger system

of economic exchanges in which individual

societies figure as elements.  At the very

least there must be some sort of core/periphe-

ry structure, and this structure must have a

hierarchical organization such that at least

some minimal degree of "development of under-

development" occurs.  This implies some sort

of dominance of the core and an exploitative

relationship between the core and the periphe-

ry.  It seems very dubious that the relations

among stateless societies can be characterized

in such a way, at least as a regular and

systematic feature.  What I think we are

dealing with here are what might be called

world-networks: loose exchange relationships

in which the parts of the whole maintain great

autonomy.

   When we turn to the other types of world-

systems Chase-Dunn proposes, I think we also

have to exercise caution.  I agree that there

were world- economies and world-empires throu-

ghout the precapitalist era after the rise of

civilization and the state, and I agree that

these world-systems may well have had a core/-

periphery kind of structure and at least

something that could be described as the

development of underdevelopment.  Yet I am

concerned about pushing this idea too far, for

the parallels between the modern capitalist

world-system and earlier world-systems may be

rather limited.  As Phil Kohl has remarked in

an attempt to apply a world-system model to

the Bronze Age Near East (1987:16):

 

 

   There is little reason to doubt that

   patterns of dependency or, perhaps bet-

   ter, interdependency were established as

   a result of intercultural exchange in

   the Bronze Age world-system. . . . De-

   pendency could lead to exploitation, and

   . . . the more powerful urban societies

   could dictate the terms of the exchange.

   But the relations between ancient cores

   and peripheries were not structurally

   analogous to those which underdevelop-

   ment theorists postulate are character-

   istic of First-Third World relations

   today. Unless conquered (i.e., incorpo-

   rated into a larger polity), ancient

   peripheries could have followed one of

   several options ranging from with-drawal

   from the exchange network to substitu-

   tions of one core partner for another.

   Archaeological and historical evidence

   converge to suggest  that most intercul-

   tural exchange systems in antiquity were

   fragile, lasting at most a few genera-

   tions before collapsing.  This inherent

   instability is related to the relative

   weakness of the bonds of dependency that

   existed between core and peripheral

   partners.

 

 

Even in the case of world-empires, it remains

to be shown that dependency and the develop-

ment of underdevelopment closely corresponded

to what prevails in our modern world-system.

 

 

 

 

 

 

THE EVOLUTIONARY LOGICS OF WORLD-SYSTEMS

 

 

Although Chase-Dunn's work on world-systems is

at this point substantially typological, he

has not failed to ask about the dynamics of

these systems.  He has suggested that dif-

ferent types of world-systems have different

dynamics, or what might be called "evolutio-

nary logics," built into them.  We already

know what the evolutionary logic of the modern

capitalist world-economy is:  the ceaseless

drive for the accumulation of capital.  And we

know that this evolutionary logic was basical-

ly absent, or at least not well developed, in

precapitalist world-systems.  On what kind of

evolutionary logics, then, did the different

precapitalist world-systems depend?   In the

remainder of this paper I want to sketch the

beginnings of an answer to this question.  It

will become clear that, in the process of

doing so, I will be making some significant

modifications of Chase-Dunn's ideas.

 

 

 

 

Stateless World-Systems

 

 

Again, I want to emphasize that I do not

really accept the notion of a stateless world-

system.  That being the case, I want to argue

that the evolution of stateless societies --

bands, tribes, and chiefdoms, as they are

commonly known among anthropologists and

archaeologists -- is largely a process of

endogenous evolution.  Exchange relations

between stateless societies play only a secon-

dary, and perhaps very minor, role in the

evolutionary transformation of such systems.

What, then, is the motor of evolution in such

societies?

   The answer, I believe, has to do with the

ecological adaptations of human communities.

The two great evolutionary transformations in

the precapitalist era were the Neolithic

Revolution and the rise of civilization and

the state.  In recent years many archaeologis-

ts have implicated population pressure as a

cause of the shift from hunting and gathering

to agriculture as a mode of production.  This

variable has been given greatest prominence by

Mark Cohen (1977).  Cohen's position is that

ancient hunter-gatherers eventually outgrew

the capacity of their foraging technologies to

support them at an acceptable standard of

living.  Once this began to occur, they en-

countered a "food crisis" that could be effec-

tively solved only by the gradual replacement

of foraging by cultivation and  animal hus-

bandry.

   To my mind, the most persuasive theory of

the origin of the state is Robert Carneiro's

(1970, 1981, 1987) circumscription theory.

This theory is too well known to need more

than brief summary here.  Carneiro holds that

the earliest states developed in environments

that were highly circumscribed or impacted.

These were areas of fertile soil that had

definite geographical limits to the expansion

of human populations.  As population density

rose within these regions, warfare was set off

as a response to declining land and resource

scarcity.  Groups conquered and incorporated

other groups.  Tribes consolidated into chief-

doms, and with further increases in population

pressure and warfare chiefdoms consolidated

into states.

   One of the interesting things about Carnei-

ro's theory from the point of view of this

paper is that it is neither a strictly endoge-

nist nor a strictly exogenist theory.  Popula-

tion pressure may be regarded as an endogenous

variable, but the warfare it leads to impli-

cates many different societies in each other's

fates.  Chiefdoms and states arise only as the

result of significant intersocietal contact.

However, this contact is decidedly different

from the kind of contact (economic exchange)

that traditional world-system theory has

primarily been concerned with, and thus we are

not dealing with a world-system phenomenon in

any strict sense of that term.

   Marvin Harris (1977, 1979) has subsumed

these theories and others like them into a

general materialist theory of social evolu-

tion.  For Harris, the motor of social evolu-

tion is the need to advance technology against

the lowered living standards that inevitably

occur as a result of population pressure and

environmental degradation.  But technological

advance is only a temporary solution, for it

in turn ultimately exacerbates population

pressure and environmental degradation, thus

leading to the need for a new and more inten-

sive wave of technological change.  Social

evolution -- or at least precapitalist social

evolution -- is thus primarily a spiraling

process of environmental depletion and inten-

sification in which population growth plays a

vital role.

   For reasons that I have detailed elsewhere

(cf. Sanderson, 1988, 1990) and do not have

space to discuss here, I believe that Harris's

theory is probably our best general theory of

social evolution in stateless societies.  It

is obvious that it gives priority to the

productive forces rather than the relations of

production as the motor of change, thus putt-

ing it at a considerable remove from the

arguments that world-system enthusiasts are

advocating.  But while this may be a strength

of Harris's theory at the level of stateless

systems, it seems to be a significant weakness

when we move to the level of states and world-

systems.  At this level, the relations of

production deserve more consideration than

Harris usually gives them.

 

 

 

 

World-Empires

 

 

I shall have little to say about what Chase-

Dunn calls the primary world- economies,

simply because at this point I have not stud-

ied them sufficiently.  Basically, it seems

that Wallerstein's point that these tended

always to evolve into world-empires has little

to contradict it.  Let me then try to talk

about the evolutionary logic of world-empires.

   The conventional view of world-empires,

shared by Wallerstein, Weber, and many other

thinkers of different theoretical and politi-

cal persuasions, is that they contain strong

built-in obstacles to the movement toward some

qualitatively different kind of socioeconomic

system or mode of production.  It is during

the era of history dominated by world-empires

that we find that a cyclical, rather than an

evolutionary, theory of world history seems to

be most appropriate.  As Owen Lattimore has

said in describing the rise and fall of Chine-

se dynasties (1940:531):

 

 

   The brief chronicle of a Chinese dynasty

   is very simple: a Chinese general or a

   barbarian conqueror establishes a peace

   which is usually a peace of exhaustion.

   There follows a period of gradually in-

   creasing prosperity as land is brought

   back under cultivation, and this passes

   into a period of apparently unchanging

   stability.  Gradually, however, weak

   administration and corrupt government

   choke the flow of trade and taxes.

   Discontent and poverty spread.  The last

   emperor of the dynasty is often vicious

   and always weak -- as weak as the found-

   er of the dynasty was ruthless.  The

   great fight each other for power, and

   the poor turn against all government.

   The dynasty ends, and after an interval

   another begins, exactly as the last

   began, and runs the same course.

 

 

The theme of the absence of any real "evolu-

tionary potential" to the historic world-

empires has been echoed by Jonathan Friedman.

Friedman notes (1982:182; emphasis added)

 

 

   that while there is clearly an . . .

   evolutionary process of formation of

   states and civilizations, there is no

   obvious continuity of social evolution

   after the emergence of civilization.  It

   would appear that the regional systems

   of civilizations, with their commercial

   centers, peripheral chiefdoms and

   tribes, and marginal bands, have been

   stable organizations until the modern

   period.  While centers of accumulation

   have shifted, there has been no funda-

   mental change in form, only differences

   in dominant economic sectors -- state

   versus private -- and the form of ex-

   ploitation -- peasant, serf, slave, or

   wage labor -- that have been prevalent.

 

 

   Michael Mann (1986) has characterized the

view represented by Lattimore and Friedman as

the negative view of empires, and suggests

that it is overdrawn.  "Although the  milita-

rism of imperial states certainly had its

negative side," he argues, "it could lead to

general economic development" (1986:148).

Mann argues that the leading example of milit-

arism having a catalyzing effect on economic

development is the Roman Empire.  In this

case, militarism contributed to economic

development in a number of ways, but particul-

arly in terms of the consumption needs of the

army.  These needs greatly stimulated demand

and, hence, production (Mann refers to this as

a sort of "military Keynesianism").  In the

end, though, Mann is forced to admit that

militarism led more often to quite different

results, and that empires "contained no devel-

opment, no true dialectic" (1986:161).

   What has been said above about world-emp-

ires in general applies just as well, I think,

to what Chase-Dunn has called commercializing

world-systems.  These were systems that had an

unusual amount of mercantile activity in them.

Chase-Dunn (1986) suggests that China in the

eighth century A.D. was such a system, and

that capitalism came close to becoming domi-

nant there at the time of the Sung dynasty.

But was this really the case?  Was the situa-

tion here so different from what we find in

other world-empires?  Certainly the outcome

was basically no different for, as Chase-Dunn

himself notes, this nascent Chinese capitalism

was crushed by the state because the economic

interests of private entrepreneurs were a

significant threat to the state.

   Chase-Dunn also considers as an example --

undoubtedly the leading example -- of a com-

mercializing world-system the so-called Afro-

Eurasian super world-system.  He accepts the

argument of Schneider, Ekholm, and Abu-Lughod

that it was the character of this world-system

that led to the development of capitalism in

Western Europe in the sixteenth century.  I

would like to suggest, however, that there was

no such world-system -- there was at best only

a loose world-network of trade in which Europe

participated -- and that the transition from

feudalism to capitalism had much to do with

evolutionary forces that were endogenous to

Europe itself.  As we shall see, there was an

important exogenous dimension to the feudal-

ism-capitalism transition, but this transition

cannot be interpreted as a world-systemic

phenomenon in any strict sense of that term.

This suggests another important limitation to

the effort to apply a world-system model to

the precapitalist era.

 

 

 

 

THE EVOLUTIONARY LOGIC OF FEUDAL SYSTEMS

 

 

The Transition from Feudalism to Capitalism in

Western Europe

 

 

Any intelligent analysis of the European

transition from feudalism to capitalism must

begin with the famous debate between Maurice

Dobb and Paul Sweezy that was conducted short-

ly after the end of the Second World War.  In

his classic Studies in the Development of

Capitalism (1963; first edition 1947), Dobb

set forth a Marxist theory of the transition

that  emphasized the internal contradictions

of feudalism as a mode of production.  What

led the feudal system into crisis and ultimat-

ely tore it apart, Dobb asserted, was the

growing class struggle between landlords and

peasants.  The intensified exploitation of the

peasantry by the landlord class provoked a

peasant flight from the land that was the

major cause of the crisis and the transition.

   Sweezy (1976; orig. 1950) questioned the

basic logic of this theory by asserting that

it improperly concentrated on endogenous

forces.  He argued that there were no endoge-

nous forces within feudalism strong enough to

transform it and proposed as an alternative a

basically exogenist theory.  It was the reviv-

al, from about the eleventh century, of long-

distance trade between Europe and other world

regions that he saw as the impetus for the

feudal crisis and the move toward capitalism.

The revival of this trade caused feudalism to

be increasingly involved in a market economy.

As towns grew in size and importance, serfs

were increasingly attracted to them and they

fled the land in large numbers.  Moreover,

feudal lords themselves were increasingly

attracted by the possibilities inherent in the

market economy for the generation of large

fortunes.

   This exogenist interpretation of the rise

of capitalism bears considerable resemblance

to the recent theory of the capitalist transi-

tion being promoted by a number of world-

system enthusiasts (i.e., that the transition

was a matter of a geopolitical shift from east

to west within the Afro-Eurasian super world-

system).  By itself, it is a highly dubious

interpretation.  What strikes me most about

Sweezy's theory is its highly ethnocentric

character.  Sweezy seems to assume that the

mere existence of a system of production-for-

exchange is sufficient to pull feudal lords

away from their customary system of produc-

tion-for-use.  Again and again we see him

characterizing feudalism as a mode of produc-

tion inferior to capitalism, and he clearly

assumes that feudal lords would have seen it

that way too.

   I do not think that Sweezy's interpretation

is irrelevant to understanding the rise of

capitalism, but by itself it does not get us

very far.  As for Dobb's theory, I believe

that it is moving in the right direction by

focusing on the internal structure of feudal-

ism as a mode of production.  However, what is

wrong with this theory is Dobb's failure to

offer a convincing explanation for the flight

of serfs from the land. He attributes this to

increasing exploitation by the landlord class,

but he provides no plausible (to me at least)

reason why there should have been such an

increase in exploitation.

   There is, however, another interpretation

that can explain the things that Dobb's theory

cannot.  This theory, also an endogenist

theory, is the demographic argument put for-

ward by such scholars as Postan (1972), Wil-

kinson (1973), North and Thomas (1973), Le Roy

Ladurie (1974), and Perry Anderson  (1974a).

The argument goes something like this.  From

about the eleventh until the end of the thir-

teenth century, feudalism was undergoing

significant demographic expansion.  As popula-

tion grew, new and more marginal lands were

increasingly brought under cultivation until

eventually Europe became "filled up." By 1300

a serious state of overpopulation had been

reached.  The crisis induced by this overpopu-

lation turns out in effect to have led to its

own "cure."  Increasing famine, malnourish-

ment, and other disease -- especially the

Black Death that first swept Europe in 1348-

50 -- led to a population decline that contin-

ued until around 1450.   This population

decline led to a severe labor shortage, which

caused a dramatic fall in the incomes of the

landlord class and shifted the balance of

class power in the direction of the peasantry.

The landlord class reacted to their markedly

changed economic fortunes in a number of ways,

but especially by expropriating the peasantry

from the land and turning their estates over

to the raising of sheep in order to sell their

wool on the market.  Landlords were moving

more in the direction of becoming capitalist

farmers.  Moreover, many peasants stayed on

the land, but not as traditional serfs. They

became transformed into wageearning farmhands

who assisted their former landlords in running

a capitalist agricultural enterprise.  Some

peasants even became transformed into capital-

ists -- yeoman farmers -- themselves.

   While all of this was happening, the towns

were growing in importance.  The power and

significance of the merchants were increasing,

and the peasants who fled the land were becom-

ing a growing source of labor for the economic

activity of the towns. Now to explain all of

this I think we need to bring Sweezy's theory

back into the picture.  As Michael Mann (1986)

has asked, why did the demographic and econom-

ic crisis of feudalism get resolved in the way

it did?  Why did the landlord class react to

their declining economic fortunes by gradually

transforming themselves, and many of their

serfs, into capitalists?  Why did they not

respond to the growing power of the peasants

by intensifying their repression and exploita-

tion of the peasantry?  Mann offers a plausi-

ble answer to these questions (1986:411):

 

 

   If the feudal mode of production gave to

   the lords a monopoly of the means of

   physical violence, could they not re-

   spond with military force at times when

   relative product and factor values did

   not favor them? . . . This is not an

   idle question, for in many other times

   and places the response of lords to

   labor shortages has been to increase the

   dependency of their laborers. . . . The

   immediate answer to these questions is

   that the European lords did try repres-

   sion and they nominally succeeded, but

   to no avail.  Returning to the example

   of late-fourteenth-century labor short-

   ages, there was a wave of landlord reac-

   tion. The lords attempted with violence

   and legislation to tie the peasantry to

   the manor and to keep down wages (just

   as late Roman landlords had).  All

   across Europe the peasantry rose up in

   rebellion, and everywhere (except Swit-

   zerland) they were repressed.  But their

   lords' victory proved hollow.  The lords

   were compelled not by the peasants but

   by the transformed capitalist market and

   by opportunities for profit, and threat

   of loss, within it.  The weak state

   could not implement legislation without

   the local cooperation of the lords; it

   was the lords.  And individual lords

   gave in, leased out their demesnes, and

   converted labor services into money

   rents. . . . The feudal mode of produc-

   tion was finally broken by the market.

 

 

   Now that would be a deeply unsatisfying

   sentence -- if we stopped the explana-

   tion there.  Neoclassical economists do

   leave it there, because they assume the

   existence of a market in the first

   place.  The "market variant" of Marxism

   (e.g., Sweezy 1976) also leaves it

   there.

 

 

   So, in other words, Sweezy's exogenist

theory has a contribution to make, but only in

the context of the endogenous evolution of

feudalism itself.  The revival of long-dis-

tance trade historically converged with this

endogenous evolution, but had it not been for

the internally generated crisis of feudalism,

the revival of trade and the market could not

have transformed feudal society.  Feudalism

would have changed somewhat, but it still

would have been feudalism.  Capitalism would

never have emerged.

 

 

 

 

The Transition from Feudalism to Capitalism in

Japan

 

 

Although I find the interpretation just ad-

vanced highly convincing, some will not.  For

them it may seem, at best, only one of several

plausible interpretations.  Let me therefore

suggest an additional line of evidence that

supports my argument for the great significan-

ce of endogenous forces in the feudalism-

capitalism transition: the approximately

parallel case of Japan.

   Perry Anderson (1974b) has argued that the

feudal mode of production (in the restrictive

sense in which he conceives of it) has existed

in only one civilization outside Europe.  From

approximately the fifteenth to the nineteenth

centuries a form of feudalism very similar to

European feudalism prevailed in Japan.  In

tracing the historical development of Japanese

feudalism, Anderson has shown that it under-

went a remarkable degree of commercialization

during its evolution.  More boldly, one might

say that Japanese society underwent its own

transition from feudalism to capitalism.  From

the point of view of the concerns of this

paper, the extraordinary thing about this

transition was that it was a completely endog-

enous process. Indeed, it had to be, because

Japan sealed itself off from the rest of the

world between 1638 and its "opening" in the

middle of the nineteenth century.  During this

time Japan was a highly autonomous society

that was not part of any world-system, or even

of any much looser world-network of societies.

As Jacques Mutel has argued, in Japan "the

first accumulation of capital, as contrasted

with Europe, owed nothing to a distant over-

seas trade.  This is proof, if one were need-

ed, that one has  overestimated, if not the

place, at least the necessity of such trade in

the birth of modern society" (1988:142).

   According to the account given by Perry

Anderson, the Japanese feudal epoch was wit-

ness to a considerable commercialization of

agriculture.  In the eighteenth century there

had developed a considerable regional special-

ization, and many crops were being produced

directly for the market.  "By the end of the

[Tokugawa] Shogunate, it is clear that a

remarkably high proportion of total agricul-

tural output was commercialized" (Anderson,

1974b:448).  Mercantile activity was also

becoming much more vigorous, and many large

towns developed and grew in importance.

Anderson even speaks of a "crisis of Japanese

feudalism" that he believes had become ap-

parent by the early nineteenth century.

   Jon Halliday (1975) tells much the same

story as Anderson. Halliday makes much of the

growing importance of urban merchants during

the Tokugawa epoch, and he also describes a

process of evolution in Japan that is strik-

ingly similar to what Wallerstein has describ-

ed for Europe: a feudal aristocracy gradually

becoming bourgeois.  One might conclude from

Anderson's and Halliday's analyses that, by

the time Commodore Perry arrived in Japan in

1853, Japan remained a society that was so-

cially and politically feudal, but within a

framework that was essentially capitalist.

The economic order had changed dramatically

from the beginning of the Tokugawa Shogunate

in 1603.

   Now it must be recognized that there were

some importance differences between the Japa-

nese transition and the European one, and that

these differences were linked to Japanese

isolation.  As Anderson has commented (1974b:-

453-454):

 

 

   These sealed frontiers were henceforward

   a permanent noose on the development of

   merchant capital in Japan.  One of the

   fundamental preconditions of primitive

   accumulation in early modern Europe was

   the dramatic internationalization of

   commodity exchange and exploitation from

   the epoch of the Discoveries onwards. .

   . . The Shogunal policy of seclusion, in

   effect, precluded any possibility of a

   transition to the capitalist mode of

   production proper within the Tokugawa

   framework.  Deprived of foreign trade,

   commercial capital in Japan was con-

   stantly reined in and re-routed towards

   parasitic dependence on the feudal no-

   bility and its political systems.

 

 

   Yes, the isolation of Japan from interna-

tional economic exchanges certainly limited

its development, and thus it was only after

the opening of Japan to the West that it

really developed into, in Anderson's phraseol-

ogy, a "capitalist mode of production proper."

But the fact that it had evolved so far in the

direction of that mode of production in such a

short time, and that it had done so in virtual

seclusion, suggests that there is something

about feudalism as a mode of production  that

gives it a fundamental, endogenous impetus to

breakdown and transformation toward a specifi-

cally capitalist system.  Most everyone agrees

that the highly decentralized character of

feudalism, a character that permits merchants

a freedom of economic maneuver that is gener-

ally denied in more centralized political

systems, is a crucial aspect of this impetus.

In Europe, the demographic and ecological

limitations of feudalism also seemed to play a

vital role, as we have seen.  Was this also

the case in Japan?   Ester Boserup (1965) has

suggested that major demographic changes

occurred within Tokugawa Japan, but her argu-

ment is much disputed, and in any event our

knowledge of Japan in this area is much too

thin to give a definitive answer.

   But regardless of whether or not demograph-

ic change played a major role in the Japanese

transition from feudalism to capitalism, it

seems undeniable that this transition was a

fundamentally endogenous process in its early

phases.  If the full emergence of Japanese

capitalism was to require the participation of

Japan in the larger Europe-centered world-

economy, this only shows that exogenous fac-

tors played a significant role as well.  In

the end, then, the evolution of capitalism in

both Europe and Japan exemplifies what Hal-

liday has fittingly called "the dialectic of

the internal and the external."

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

CONCLUSIONS

 

 

This essay has been largely devoted to answer-

ing a fundamental question:  Is the basic unit

of social evolution the individual society or

some sort of world-system?  The answer, of

course, is that it is both.  But when it is

the one, and when the other, depends very much

on circumstances.  In the case of stateless

societies, most social evolution is internal

to societies themselves, the most important

stimuli to evolutionary change being popula-

tion pressure and environmental degradation.

In the case of the two great feudal civiliza-

tions of world history, it would also seem

that societies rather than world-systems are

the appropriate unit.  After all, neither

feudal Europe nor feudal Japan constituted

world-systems, even in the form of world-econ-

omies.  In the case of feudal Europe there

existed one of the features that Wallerstein

has identified as basic to a world-system,

viz., a multiplicity of cultures.  But al-

though these cultures interacted, they did not

do so via the existence of the type of econom-

ic specialization -- a core/periphery hierar-

chy -- that is a crucial defining feature of a

world-system.

   That still leaves us with a fair amount of

room for the application of a world-system

perspective to social evolution. Much of what

went on in agrarian civilizations of the past

no doubt can -- and often must -- be analyzed

from the point of view of their involvement in

larger world-economies and world-empires

(although, again, the impetus to evolutionary

transformation is very weak; disintegration,

or dynastic cycles, were the rule).  Then

there is our modern capitalist world-economy.

Wallerstein and others have convincingly

demonstrated, that to my satisfaction at

least, the modern world-system is the basic

unit of analysis for understanding the evolu-

tion of the individual societies that are part

of it.  This does not mean that factors endog-

enous to individual societies play no role.

It simply means that those factors can exert

their effects only within the context of the

constraints of the larger system.  As Waller-

stein (1985:35) has elegantly put it, "It is

not that there are no particularities of each

acting group. Quite the contrary.  It is that

the alternatives available for each unit are

constrained by the framework of the whole,

even while each actor opting for a given

alternative in fact alters the framework of

the whole."

 

 

 

 

 

 

                         NOTES